I continue the topic of blunders and squiggles, begun in the article "Blunders of textbooks and curiosities of study . " I recall the definitions:- Blooper is a blatant or veiled mistake, which is not, however, of a fundamental nature, so that after suffering, you can fix it.
- Zagogulina is a phrase, a theme set forth in such a way that to understand it one needs to smash one’s head (ordinary, not genius and not talent).
1. What is the simplicity of the formula?
Take the book “Probability Theory. Basic concepts. Limit Theorems. Random processes ”, Yu.V. Prokhorov, Yu.A. Rozanov,“ Science ”, 1967. Iquote the text on page 14:“ Stirling formula. In all the above formulas, the expression. The direct calculation of such a product for large n is very laborious. There is a relatively simple formula giving an approximate value for n !, called the Stirling formula: for large n
A similar phrase is found in other books and on the Internet.I don’t understand something than the Stirling formula is simpler than the defining formula . In what respect is easier? How to arrange formulas by simplicity? Since the key phrase was “Direct calculation of such a product for large n is very laborious”, it is natural to assume greater simplicity in the sense of fewer calculations. Okay, let's come from this side. Compare the formulas from the position of the number of elementary operations (from the point of view of a computer) in one and the other formulas. In the formulathere are n multiplications. In the Stirling formula, we have the operations:- - two multiplications and one root extraction. Extracting the root is not an elementary operation, but its implementation requires a computational cycle and the longer, the greater the required accuracy of the calculations.
- - n multiplications. . After all, we will not dissemble, that this is one operation. In this case, we can say that n! one operation. At least in no computer, neither degree nor exponential function is elementary operation.
- - this is also not an elementary operation, but its implementation requires a computational cycle and the longer, the greater the required accuracy of the calculations.
The funniest thing is that declared easier . From any point of view on simplicity, after this one can no longer reason further.So, it is clear that from the point of computational complexity, the Stirling formula is in no way simpler than the defining formula.So why then do we need the Stirling formula? There is no universal answer. And it does not come down to simplicity of calculations. It all depends on the situation. For example, it is unlikely to simplify the expressionyou need to apply the Stirling formula. The defining formula immediately gives.In general, if we have an identity like formula1 ≡ formula2, then sometimes it is beneficial to replace formula1 with formula2, and sometimes vice versa.In some situations, the application of the Stirling formula leads to an obvious reduction in the terms of the formula where it enters, which is difficult to see if the defining formula is applied. At least in statistical physics this is so. There, all fundamental quantities are expressed in terms of statistical weight, the formulas for which are flickered with factorials. But entropy, for example, is expressed through the natural logarithm of the number of states. This is where the role of form begins to play, in this case, the representation of the factorial through the degree:And here is an example of the application of the Stirling formula, taken from Fichtenholtz (v.2):
2. The catch of the notation
Take the textbook “Physics of Elementary Particles”, author N.F. Nelipa, Moscow, “Higher School”, 1977. On page 19, the relation between the momentum and coordinate representations is recorded:We see that the formula contains both φ on the right and φ on the left. If this is an identity, then looking at this formula, a not very sophisticated person can draw these conclusions.We take φ (x) = 1Then from (1) we have
1=(1/(2π)2)∫dpe−ipx1
Got a “wonderful” decomposition of unity. Or, similarly,
sin(x)=(1/(2π)2)∫dpe−ipxsin(p)
All this is clearly nonsense. So what's the deal?Or maybe relation (1) should be interpreted as an equation of the typex2=bx?We look at other books. Here is another “Physics of Elementary Particles”, author Gaziorovich, Moscow, “Science”, 1969. On page 20 we have the formulaφ(x)=(1/(2π)2)∫dpe−ipxφ̃(p) (2)
I breathe a sigh of relief. This is just a connection between the coordinate and momentum representations and it is given from the point of view of mathematics by the Fourier expansion. Here φ and φ ̃ are different functions. But what about formula (1) Nelips? From the point of view of mathematics, it is incorrect. If φ is a function, then both φ (x) and φ (p) are all one function. I was tormented for a long time (“The author cannot help but notice this. That means the case is trickier”) and then found an excuse from the point of view of physics. Here it is:φ (x) and φ (p) are not the same functions, they are one and the same field φ taken in different representations. The field is one, but its presentation is different. The view type is specified by a letter in brackets. We focus on the fact that the field does not change. The view is changing. So I reassured myself.But, gentlemen, the authors, you are writing a textbook. explain to mere mortals what’s what. And then the reader has to find excuses for the author .Further, I turn to the Soviet quantum classics “Introduction to the Theory of Quantized Fields” by NN Bogolyubov and DV Shirkov, Nauka, Moscow, 1973. Page 28.φ(x)=(1/(2π)3/2)∫dke−ikxφ̃(k) (3)
Fine. And the aforementioned Gaziorovich is similar. But, look further. I quote:“... we find that the function φ ̃ (k) satisfies the equation
(k2−m2)φ̃(k)=0
And, therefore, can be represented asφ̃(k)=δ(k2−m2)φ(k)
And, further, it is said that with this in mind, decomposition (3) will take the formφ(x)=(1/(2π)3/2)∫dke−ikxδ(k2−m2)φ(k) (4)
Again we returned to the representation of φ through φ. From understandable Gaziorovich came to the incomprehensible Nelipe. What does it mean? Is this an equation? I think that here too it is necessary to give an interpretation similar to the case of Nelipa given above.This is really a squiggle. For some reason, this squiggle met me only in the books of Soviet authors.And I will return to the author of Nelip. We take his book “Physics of elementary particles. Gauge Fields. ” The book is recommended as a study guide. This obliges the textbook to make all kinds of defaults as little as possible. No need to force the student to think long about solving the defaults. It’s already difficult for him. However, we take the formula (1.2.14) and the preceding text:Matricesλk satisfy the following commutation relations (Lie algebra):[λk,λj]−=2ifkjnλn,Spλiλjk=2δij (1.2.14)
And not a word is said that summing is meant by n. This is neither in the preface nor in the main text. And there are a lot of such formulas in the book.Moreover, the introduction says:“The scalar product of two four-dimensional vectors is written as(ab)=aμbμ=a0b0−a1b1−a2b2−a3b3=a0b0−(ab)Does this rule apply to (1.2.14) or not? The indices are repeated there, but there are no four-dimensional vectors.And all because Nelipa decided not to distinguish between contravariant and covariant vectors and, thereby, get rid of superscripts. They distinguished a contravariant vector (ordinary vector) from a covariant (covector, shape). Usually the upper index spoke about contravariance, and the lower one about covariance. Then, observing Einstein’s rule and considering thataμ=gμνaν,gμν=diag{1,−1,−1,−1} we have aμbμ=a0b0+a1b1+a2b2+a3b3=a0b0−a1b1−a2b2−a3b3In general, I stopped reading Nelipa’s books.3. Large squiggle measurements
3.1. Dirac
We read his Principles of Quantum Mechanics:A, , , . A , , . , , . , , a, , , . , . , , measurement always causes a jump in the system into the eigenstate of that dynamic variable, the measurement of which was carried out, and the eigenvalue to which this eigenstate relates is equal to the measurement result
3.2. Landau
We read it “Quantum mechanics. Nonrelativistic theory ":If the electron was in a state Ψn(q), then the measurement fdetect with certainty the value fn. But after measurement, the electron will be able toφn(q)different from the original, in which the value fno longer has any specific meaning. Therefore, if we performed a second measurement on the electron immediately after the first one, we would get forf , . ( ) φn(q), – Ψn(q), . .
φn(q,t), φn(q). m- , t, ∫φn(q,t)Ψm∗(q)dq.
We see that the measurement process in quantum mechanics has a two-faced character - its role in relation to the past and the future does not coincide. In relation to the past, it verifies the probabilities of various possible outcomes predicted from the state created by the previous dimension. In relation to the future, it creates a new state. Thus, in the very nature of the measurement process lies deep irreversibility. It introduces into physical phenomena the physical nonequivalence of both directions of time, i.e. leads to a distinction between past and future.
3.3. Blokhintsev
We read his "Fundamentals of Quantum Mechanics":, , “ ”, .
, .
. () . , .
, , .. .
This transformation of a pure ensemble into a mixed one is nothing more than the practical implementation of the spectral decomposition of the original ensemble into a spectrum according to the pure ensembles that the instrument collects.
A classical measuring device is nothing but a spectral analyzer of quantum ensembles, with the help of which their nature is studied.
3.4. Susskind
We read it “Quantum mechanics. Theoretical minimum. ”… . . , . , , . . LL. ? . . , . .
. L
|Ψ>=∑iαi|λi>
|αj|2λjL, |λj>. .
( — ) . ?
. . .
3.5.
Feynman has, in my opinion, the best in general physics textbook on quantum mechanics. This is a great book, Quantum Mechanics. However, in it he does not interpret the measurement results anywhere. But there appeared their squiggles, which led me to a standstill. But more about that another time. 3.6. Wihman
He has a book called Quantum Physics, which is part of the excellent Berkeley physics course. Here is a quote from the paragraph “Is it possible in principle to predict the outcome of each measurement?”, , . , , . , , . «» . . 4 , , . , , , «» .
, , , . ( ), .
, . , , , . ,
3.7.
So, we have two alternative points of view:- If measuring observable Awe got the result ajthen after measurement the system is in a state |aj>. This is the so-called projection postulate . The name comes from where. Prior to measurement, the state vector can be represented as|Ψ>=∑ici|ai>. And after the measurement we have|Ψ′>=|aj>. Or, mathematically speaking, the dimension projects the original vector|Ψ> on one of the axes (the j axis in this case), numbered by the index i, in the expansion |Ψ>=∑ici|ai>
- If measuring observable Awe got the result aj, this does not mean that after measurement the system is in a state |aj>. But this state can be determined by solving the Schrödinger equation, which describes the interaction of the device and the measured system.
And another alternative:a) Between measurements, the state vector changes deterministically in accordance with the Schrödinger equation. During measurement, the state vector collapses in a non-deterministic manner. This is the postulate of non-deterministic reduction .b) Between measurements, the state vector changes deterministically in accordance with the Schrödinger equation. And during measurement, the state vector changes in a deterministic manner in accordance with the Schrödinger equation, into which the Hamiltonian of the interaction of the measured system and the measuring device is introduced.Why do different interpretations not interfere with the applications of quantum mechanics?But becauseall examples discussed in textbooks deal with evolution from preparation to measurement. And it is described by the Schrödinger equation .Now who is right? I think Landau is right, following alternatives 2. and b).Further, the following notation will apply:A - observable physical quantity a- result of measurement of observable A, |a>Is the eigenvector of the observed Acorresponding to the eigenvalue a.Here is a certain argument for the above statement about who is right. 3.7.1. Denial of the projection postulate
If measuring observable Awe got the result a, then this does not mean anything else, except that we got a. This does not mean that after measurement the system is in a state|a>. This does not say anything about the state of the system before the measurement. But if with multiple measurement of the quantityA over a prepared ensemble, statistics give meaning aiwith frequency cici∗- then the ensemble before the measurement is described by the wave function|Ψ>=∑ici|ai>Where A|ai>=ai|ai>After the measurement, it will be described by another wave function, which is found as a solution of the Schrödinger equation recorded for the device + object interaction.If we solve the problem of the interaction of the microsystem and the classical macrosystem, then it is natural to resort to the Schrödinger equation and, at some stage, involve the classical property of the macrosystem. And suddenly we find out that the macro-system is a measuring instrument of the micro-system's characteristics and, therefore, according to the Copenhagen interpretation, the Schrödinger equation is not applicable. This is somehow unphysical. Take, for example, the calculation of the trajectory of a high-energy electron flying through a bubble chamber in a particle’s magnetic field (trajectory visualizer). If we let physics solve the problem of the motion of a high-energy electron in a supercooled liquid located in a magnetic field, then he will begin to think how to apply quantum mechanics than to neglect ... in general, he will begin to solve the problem. And what if he was announced that he was calculating the measurement process and he,remembering the Copenhagen interpretation, he will cry out that everything is going on abruptly, and that this is not subject to the Schrödinger equation and that means there is nothing to consider ... I won’t believe ...In general, different interpretations of the measurement did not prevent the development of quantum mechanics, where only processes obeying the dynamic equation of quantum mechanics were considered. What happened after the measurement, it did not matter. But in recent years they started talking about the nonlocality of quantum mechanics. And this is precisely connected with the interpretation of the dimension. If the measurement creates a state, then when measuring the subsystem of the entangled system, the value of the observed and the second unmeasured subsystem is automatically measured. And since measurement creates a state, we get instant creation of the state of the second subsystem. Even if the second subsystem diverged from the first to light years. Here is a paradox. It does not arise if you adhere to the point of view that measurement does not create, but discovers. Like in the classics. But in the classics, the discovered state will remain with him in the near future - the dynamics start with the detected initial condition begins with it. In quantum mechanics, after measurement there will be a completely different state, unknown in the general case. If this coordinate was measured and the measured system did not disappear, then according to the special theory of relativity, the coordinate will not change much in a short time. And if the impulse, then after measurement it can be any other. It all depends on the measurement process: measurement through the Compton effect, measurement along the curvature of the trajectory in a magnetic field, etc. - after each of them there will be, generally speaking, a different result.Further, the reduction postulate gives an easy way to prepare a state vector, which is an eigenvector of the observedA. Enough to measureA. Is it too easy?May we measureA and get the value a. If you adhere to the projection postulate, then after measurement the system is in a state|a>. So if we re-measureAthen we get a. And according to the postulate of reduction, the system after measurement will be in|a>. Etc. That means an endless series of measurementsA will give us meaning aand condition |a>. Isn't it strange? It seems strange to me. 3.7.2. Denial of non-deterministic reduction
Here the denial is not so much physical as epistemological. If the act of measurement does not obey the Schrödinger equation, this introduces a kind of dualism into quantum mechanics as a theory. On the one hand, before the measurement, the state vector changes deterministically, and during the measurement it is not known what and, moreover, it is unknown what is some kind of thing in itself, inaccessible to theory. From this point of view, even Newtonian mechanics are more consistent. She explained everything deterministically. 3.8. Summary
The measurement of the observable can be represented in two stages:Preparation . Its output is the measurable ensembleDimension . Its output is the value of the measured quantity and a certain new state of a new ensemble 3.8.1. Cooking
A cooking appliance prepares the system in a specific state. That this is so is checked by a measuring instrument and checked statistically by a series of measurements over the prepared ensemble. Examples of preparatory devices: a prism preparing a mixture of pure states - light, of a certain length; the Stern-Gerlach device is a “prism” for particles with a spin; particle accelerator; telescope. The prep is not measuring . Between the input and output, the system obeys the Schrödinger equation, which takes into account the interaction of the system and the cooking device. In the Stern-Gerlach device, this is the interaction of the magnetic moment of the particle and the magnetic field of the device. 3.8.2. Measurement
The measuring device detects a specific value of the measured value. Examples of measuring instruments: eye, voltmeter, ammeter, Geiger counter. After the measurement, the system, if it is not destroyed by the measurement, goes into some other state. Between the input and output of the measurement, the system obeys the Schrödinger equation, which takes into account the interaction of the system and the measuring device. Measuring instrument observableA, does not necessarily prepare the state after measurement |a>.A measurement over an ensemble in which observable values are detected determines state information prior to the measurement. The reading of the device is created as an integral characteristic of the measurement process and acquires the completed value after the measurement, as a result of some physical interaction between the meter and the measured system, the measured state of which is prepared before the measurement. When measuring, some kind of physical process occurs. And specifically, for this, it is necessary to solve the dynamic equation of interaction of the measured system and the meter (the Schrödinger time equation in the nonrelativistic case). What is really prepared after the measurement - this will show the measurement over the state prepared after the measurement. This may be a new state of the original system, or it may be that there is nothing left of the original system. Last maybefor example, when measuring the photon energy by its absorption method.Almost aphorism: cooking |a>does not measure A, and the measurement Adoesn't cook |a>. This is where the uncertainty relation arises for additional processes of preparation and measurement.